History of Christian Thought: 405-1650

History of Christian Thought: 405-1650
George Lindbeck

1/13/93
According to Wilkins, there are two uses of historical theology: critical historical analysis (intellectual history) and theological analysis of historic Christian thought (a prescriptive element).  For instance, Abelard distinguished authentic versus inauthentic teachings.  He discussed four ways to account for differences in theology: ingenuine quotes, retractions, changes in the meaning of terms, and a later finding of incorrectness of views once thought to be correct (e.g. the creation doctrine and divine simplicity).  Aquinus wrote a treatise on theological method in which he argued that changed settings may necessitate different theological methods and terms.   But neither theologian, nor those before them, accounted for doctrinal change on historical grounds.  In the 1600’s, theology was conceived of as having a history, and this was recognized as a field.  Salomo Semler, for instance, argued that theology is shaped by times.  In the early 1800’s, historical theology was established as a separate discipline.  In the 1900’s, the field became dominated by historians, with a greater awareness of social forces and a better ‘heretic’ analysis. The focus is the intellectual history of Christianity, where the settings of the theologies is salient.   But, this entailed a historical filter of theology where God isn’t in the center of the work and with a loss of understanding and depth.  The assumption is that past texts only have theological relevance if they are translated into the categories of our age.  But early Christian texts such as the Bible are not just for past times, so the native language of Christianity is for today.  Christian terms and concepts grow out of concrete historical settings, so recourse to historical writings and settings is necessary in understanding Christianity.  Because historical writings are influenced by their times, it is necessary to understand the times too.  There must, however, be a theological point of reference (God—the unity among the diversity).  The aim of the field of Historical Theology is finding God (as the trinity).  But, the trinity is not accepted as classically established by all demonstrations (i.e. excludes some people).  Wilkins argues that the means are spiritual as well as intellectual, loving God above all else.  Perception is important but not critical in seeing how the texts fit together to fit into a whole with internal coherence.
Lindbeck argues that Wilkins can be criticized as excluding the voices of some, such as liberation theologists.  Discipleship may allow Church powers to exclude some scholars (e.g. heretics).  Also, Wilkins can’t account for diversity at one time.  Abelard and Aquinas, for instance.  Lindbeck looks for similarities where others saw differences.
Richard Norris, too, argues that the setting influences theology.  Faith in a community is historical as well as present.  Tradition implies a ‘handing on’—active, maintaining Christian experience. 
Rano argues that the object of faith is the faith of the Church.  He emphasizes the scientific quality too.  But, like Watkins, the object of this is faith today. 
Peligan argues that the object is good history.  The method and criterion must be that of historians, yet working in a conversation with theologians.  He sees a danger in historicism.  Therefore, there is a tension between doctrinal continuity and truth (though he has no criterion on ‘truth’).  Like Wilkin, he tries to be objective even as the goal is to understand tradition for today.  Therefore, this field can inform one’s theology today. 

1/15/03
The focus of this course is Soteriology in Western theology within traditional christological and Trinitarian doctrines.  The doctrine of justification and sanctification (how saved and growing in grace), nature and grace, sin (harmatology), predestination (relation to free will), atonement, and the means of grace (eucharist and pentance).  Other related topics include the relationship between reason (philosophy) and faith (theology). 
St. Augustine (born in 354).
 His first text was On the Spirit and the Letter (416).  It was an anti-Pelagius document.  Plagius (born in 360) was a British monk and a reforming voice within Rome.  In 406, the Pelagian controversy began.  Pelagius looked at Augustine’s Confessions, focusing on a prayer which assumes the impossible—that one can do what God asks.  Pelagius argued that we can do what God commands.  Pelagius’ reform movement held that 1) humans don’t lose freedom in choosing the good, 2) sinfulness is resistable because we are born good (so bonds of sin are due to habit, custom, or disposition, 3) grace is not required but is a gift from God which can help.  Grace is the gift of having a good nature.  Nature is grace.  Grace also includes external aids, such as the ten commandments and the example of Jesus.  Pelagius looked like a defender of traditional Christianity, but was actually a reformer.  Augustine, in constrast, looked like an innovator but was actually quite traditional.  Christians before Pelagius emphasized freedom (rather than predestination).  Augustine had emphasized it earlier when arguing against the Gnostics. Grace had been considered liberation from powers of sin by virtue of entering the Church.  Then it became the distinction between nominal and real Christians.  To Pelagius, grace qua forces holding us captive became individual habit rather than a cosmic force.  So self advancement, and even sinlessness, became possible.  Paul distinguished inner (rational/law/will) from outer (law of the mind) law.  Pelagius claimed that outer law included accidentally acquired habits.  Augustine: this imports pagan philosophy into Paul.  To Pelagius, freedom of will (inner law/rational) makes us capable of being good.   Knowledge and free will (good nature) is sufficient for virtue.  The was Greek philosophy: if one knows what is good, one can do it.
Augustine, in response, argues for praise and thanksgiving, in place of Plagian pride and ingratitude. The broad question was how to become just/righteous/saved.  Pelagius claimed that one could be saved by knowledge of the ten commandments and the example of Jesus, and free-will(choice).  Augustine, like Pelagius, believed in free will and good nature.  But unlike Pelagius, Augustine held that sin is not accidentally acquired.  One is born sinful.  Due to original sin, we lost the choice to do good.  Therefore, more is needed than knowledge and good nature to do good.  This is contrary to Greek philosophy.  One needs an infusion of grace as well as aids to transform mind and will. 
Augustine’s neo-platonic philosophy:
The doctrine of illumination.  Plato: understanding of suprasensations(of universals).  Knowledge is from god within (the illuminator—allows us to understand universals in a human way).  Augustine: the inner teacher is Jesus Christ, for everyone whether they know it or not.  So human knowledge depends on the divine.  Pelagius: not so, as we are born with a good nature.  To Augustine, love and faith, too, are dependent upon God (infused grace within).  Grace is the indwelling holy spirit, via love enabling Christ to be effective.  So one can love God only via the Holy Spirit.  We can consent to the truth only by love given by God.

1/19/93
Augustine’s On the Spirit and the Letter.  Theses: against Plagian Pride.  Salvation requires grace beyond God’s free gifts of free-will and human nature.  This help is as an infused grace via the indwelling of the Holy Spirit (love).  The argument is as follows.  2 Cor 3:6  The letter kills but the spirit keeps alive. The issue is how to interpret this verse.  To Augustine, the letter is law (e.g. the Commandments)—what we ought to do.  Without infused grace, it kills.  Pelagius, in contrast, maintained that the letter that kills is the literal interpretation of the law; figurative interpretation is the spirit.  Augustine agrees with this interpretation, but argues that it is not sufficient—literal and figurative differences is not necessarily the main distinction in a given verse.  Augustine is against the view holding that the letter is Jewish laws whereas the spirit is Christ’s laws.  In the new law (Christ’s) are included most Jewish laws, so there is not a distinction between literal old and new laws. Rather, the contrast is between how the laws are obeyed: in love (the spirit) or done for oneself to gain salvation (the letter which kills).  Augustine uses scripture in his arguments.  He cites Phil 2:13[1] to emphasize what God gives us over what had been given to us as human nature.  He interprets the verse in line with his view of grace (infused).  Spirit and Letter show that scripture as a whole supports Augustine’s view of grace.  Augustine makes more sense of scripture than Pelagius does.  It is important to account for the scope or ‘gestalt’ of the scripture.  Criterion: what interpretation best fits scripture as a whole.  The theses of Augustine are not abstract propositions independent of the scripture, but are guidelines for illuminating the meaning of scripture—a way of reading scripture.   Yet, Augustine does not argue via doctrines; he uses scriptural exigesis.  Augustine came up with the doctrine of original sin (which led to the loss of freedom).  This doctrine was not used to argue Spirit and Letter.  Lex orandi (the patterns of prayer appealed to) is missing in Spirit and Letter.  The neo-platonic outlook of Augustine is not appealed to.  Such extra-scriptural appeals are not used.  But Augustine’s ontology, based on neo-Platonic philosophy, is used in the theses. 
A three-tiered ontology: God, Soul, Bodies.  Emminationist—increasing diversity as God flows downward, then back up in concentration.  The universe is a flowing circularity—a flowing out ofrom the one and back again.  Augustine argued that everyone can engage in upward contemplation via infused grace, thus returning back upwards.  Aristotle had held that only a few could do that.  Augustine’s modification of neo-platonic ontology: return back upwards via love in the infused grace (including infants due to the grace of baptism).  Augustine did not modify the following: higher can effect lower, not vice versa. Evil is a deprivation of the good (privatio bioni). This is neo-platonic.  Evil does not mean non-being.  Evil is a privation rather than a deficiency.  Given the neo-platonic hierarchical scheme and that lower things can’t have power over things higher (lower things can’t turn back upward by one’s own power), one can not make up lost ontological being without grace infused by God.  E.g. original sin due to the Fall, so grace is necessary for man to do good.  While the neo-platonic structure is behind Augustine’s interpretation of grace, it is not used in the argument in Spirit & Letter; instead, scripture was used there.  This is why that text had long-lasting appeal. 
Consequences: relatively broad appeal of Spirit & Letter because the reader need not hold Augustine’s other doctrine to agree with Spirit & Letter.  The two theses: help beyond nature is infused.  This is minimal Augustinianism(semi-Plageianism), affirmed by the Councils of Carthage and Ephasis.  Moderate Augustinianism adds the prevenience of grace (not in Spirit & Letter).  While the call of grace is necessary for one to do good, one can respond or not respond to the grace.  The consent is our own, rather than being of grace.  With total prevenience, the consent to grace is from God.  Roman Catholics believe this.

1/20/93
Augustine’s Spirit & Letter answers three questions.  How does one become righteous?  By the spirit-grace, enabling one to like doing the good (delight is part of love).  Augustine had distinguished between two kinds of love: love as happiness, as directed to a goal which is delightful as itself (e.g. beauty as intrinsically delightful), and love as a means toward such a goal (God as the only thing to be loved for its sake; the highest good. For everything else, to be loved as a means toward God.[2]  In Spirit & Letter, love is delight, so the need for grace is self-evident.  The core of Augustine’s argument is that via grace one receives delight/love in the good.  Augustine uses scripture to support this thesis that love is delight.  Augustine also answers the question of how we get grace.  Faith.  Therefore, if we pray for grace in the belief that God is merciful, God will give us grace.  Faith is necessary to pray for the faith which gives grace.  Augustine also answers how we get faith.  Grace preceeds faith.  But will is necessary too. 
Minimum Augustinianism: need for grace, and grace has an infused character.  Moderate Augustianianism: prevenience: God starts anything good.  The gap is closed; God is behind the choice to ask for grace.  Conservatives claimed that humans have to be able to freely respond.  Augustine replied that this freedom is from grace.  1 Cor. 4-7: even the free response is a gift (grace).  But, how can a gift involve freedom?  To Augustine, freedom can mean ability, voluntary/willingness, or liberium arbitrium (free choice; consenting or not).  Grace: once it is given to me, I am free (voluntary) to respond.  So Augustine views free will in the sense of being voluntary.  In his Retractions, Augustine went on to claim that if one is to maintain dependence on God, desire itself for faith must be a gift from God.  Single predestination is part of moderate Augustinianism.  It implies total prevenience.  God gives grace to those whom He elects.  So grace is not given due to merit; merit itself is a product of grace. 
Strong Augustinianism: irresistible grace, perseverance (grace must continue to be affirmed because grace is necessary for us to respond or affirm), and double predestination (from beginning, a predisposition to salvation as well as others damned.  Irresistable grace: if those whom God predestines are saved, then grace must be irresistible.  So we are not responsible for our own refusal to grace (unlike total prevenience).  God chooses some to save and others to damn (so not universalism).  Augustine seems to suggests these points in his later writings, but he doesn’t explicitly affirm them.  Refusing to choose God, this is a defect; due to the weakness of one’s will—due to the Fall.  So single predestination need not become double predestination.  God chooses some to be saved; others don’t have the freedom to be saved.  God doesn’t choose the latter.  Some human responsibility.    Semi-Plagianism: minimal Augustinianism, plus rejecting moderate Augustinianism.  The Council of Orange affirmed minimal and moderate Augustinianism.  The eastern church understood infusion; we are saved via incorporation in Jesus Christ, so our humanity comes to share in his divinity.  This is incompatible with Plegianism (save oneself).  So this conflict didn’t occur in the East. 
The Council of Orange:
When Augustine was old, ‘conservatives’ such as John Cassian and Vincent Lerius objected to the Antinoianism of Augustine.  In Augustine’s theology, there was a place for irresponsibility due to the doctrines of prevenience and perseverance.  Vincent Lerius wrote a famous treatise against Augustine, casting his position as an innovation which had misled Popes.  This controversy went on for about 100 years.  Then in 509, the Pope suggested that 14 bishops assemble at Orange to affirm theses of his own.  These affirm a moderate Augustinianism, against double predestination as well as the position of the conservatives. 
Augustine presumes original sin.  But his Spirit & Letter is more positive, only saying that we can’t reach delight alone.

1/22/93
Augustine held that humans are helpless to save themselves by their own power; we are totally dependent upon grace.  This view is related to his understanding of sin.  Our complete helplessness is either a consequence of our own finitude as created creatures, or is the result of our Fall (product of sin).  The emphasis in on our helplessness, as a result of sin (the Fall, or original sin).  For Augustine’s opponents, finitude plays a larger role.  Why has Augustine’s view of salvation by grace alone been found to be appealing?  How can people be righteous?  Justification.  How?  That is the question.  Pelagius claimed that humans are born good.  So there is no problem with the salvation of unbaptised infants.  This was the more popular view.  Augustine, in contrast, believed that humans are born bad due to original sin.  Both men believed that Christian faith is necessary for salvation.  Augustine’s view is seen as more pastoral, and as a good argument against Pelagian Pride.
Peter Brown wrote Augustine by Hippo, a good biography including the sociology of Pelagius v. Augustine.  Pelagius is sen as an elite movement—as self-righteous ‘puritans’.  Augustine is seen as pastorally pleasing but in fostering irresponsibility.  Augustine counters that the law should be followed because to do so shows the presence of grace.  Augustine is viewed as harsh on humans, but Pelagius’ emphasis on free-will came across as rigorous on what humans must do.  For Augustine, predestination is not the starting-point. 

529-604: The empire collapsed in the West, but the culture remained.  Then, cultural change occurred from 604 to 767.  Then, the Carolingian period (767-877).  In 800, Charlemaign was crowned emperor of the Holy Roman Empire.  The emperor had control of the continent of Europe.  Relative peace ensued, allowing some flourishing of the arts and theology.  Discussion of the real presence of the eucharist (focus on the elements of it).  It was novel for there to be treatices on a sacrament.  The discussion on the relationship of the elements to Jesus Christ’s body and blood, continued through the centuries.  A  focus on Jesus Christ exclusively.  The authors of the Carolingian period had German ancestory and language. A problem: classical Latin was a foreign language; only a clerical elite learned it.  Trying to understand texts in a foreign language was problematic.  A period of transmission, to repeat what was written in the past.  This wasn’t what actually happened.  For instance, Alguinn quoted Augustine on the trinity, but only from a selection of Augustine’s works.  Ratroundness quoted the Fathers.  Robertous started on his own. 
By 604, there had been economic, political, and social collapse.  Illiterate barbarians had taken over and didn’t know enough to keep the political/economic/social systems up.  Forests came back.  By 767, the population had declined, and some cities and agrarian areas disappeared. What was left were some clearings and villages here and there.  The Holy Roman Empire exercised only superficial control.  But, after Gregory, there was cultural discontinuity.  Learning was done in monestaries.  Via the liturgy, these social/political/economic changes affected theology.  Monks misunderstood ancient texts because they didn’t have the liturgy of the old.  The Church had changed from counter-cultural to be coexistant with society.  In Augustine’s time, infant baptism was not popular; most people joined the church as adults.  In the Carolingian period, however, there was infant baptism and no general preparation for becoming a Christian.  This meant that there had been a change in what the liturgically important event was.  Whereas in the early church, people were baptized as adults, in Carolingian times the eucharist was viewed as a continuation of infant baptism.  

1/22/93: Discussion
Augustine: at what point does grace engage the human?  What room is there for free agency?  Why do some withhold consent?  Letter & Spirit deals with grace and free agency.  It might be asked whether the unexampled life is possible.  Free-will itself is God’s gift.  Our will is severely impaired and so too is our nature.  Nature and grace are intertwined.  Will is both nature and grace.  We speak of grace as if it were a thing; rather, grace is a relationship between God and the soul.   Pelagius: knowledge if law is necessary for righteousness.  Assp: if you know what to do, you will do it.  Augustine: knowledge is necessary but not sufficient.  One needs not only knowledge and the example of Jesus Christ, but the infused Holy Spirit as well.  Augustine wants to hold on to both grace (associated with righteousness) and free will (associated with sin), with the good due to God and evil due to humans.  In later years, Augustine emphasized predestination, deemphasizing free-will.  The human will is assisted by grace, constant cooperation between them is implied.  Grace, acting on the will, plus grace (Christ quality) gives rise to a cured will.

1/25/93
In the middle ages, to be a Christian meant that one had been baptized.  Baptism and the Eurcharist were seen as reinforcing each other—baptism and the eurcharist qua becoming part of the body of Christ (participation in the crucified and risen Christ).  Later, they were separated such that baptism stood for purification/forgiveness/deliverance from original sin (i.e. infant baptism)[3].  When they were unified, only some people were baptized and received communion.  Older people were baptized (immersion, with oil/confirmation).  When they were separated, all were baptized but only some received communion, baptism was private (infant) while communion was communal (no infant eucharist), and confirmation was separated from baptism.  The benefit of the Eucharist was medicine of immortality.  During the Carolingian period, it became primary.  The liturgy was increasingly said in a foreign language (Latin) in an illiterate society.  A shift from words, elements, and objects to attention on actions and the objects.  A clerical orientation of the action (of the liturgy); the laity became spectators.  In the words of consecration, invocation of the holy spirit disappeared (in the West).  So, a concentration on the elements.  In the Carolingian period, a belief that divine power fills sacred objects.  This belief was contrary to Greek philosophy.  Church writers downplayed it.  Whereas before, the emphasis in the eucharist was its communal aspect, in the Carolingian period sacrifice (offering and consecration) was emphasized, making that liturgy central.  A shift in the Eucharist from holy people (the Church is the body of Christ, so in communion we are receiving ourselves), to holy objects. 
Ratramnus and Radbertus on the matter of the real presence in the holy objects.  They used two terms: veritas (appearance, or truth—e.g. bread and wine) and figura (inner reality concealed).  From epistemology and ontology, respectively.  Ratramnus used these terms as stated here.  Radbertus reversed them: figura is the truth while veritas is the inner reality.  According to Lindbeck, both of these theologians emphasized the body and blood as veritas.  Ratramnus emphasized figura of the presence of Christ; veritas—the bread and wine.  He used the language of the fathers which made him seem to agree with Radbertus.  Luther agreed with Radbertus while Zwingli and Calvin agreed with Ratramnus.  Both Radbertus and Ratramnus assumed that complete theological uniformity was necessary for unity. 

1/27/93
To Augustine, sacraments refer to things assigned by God whereas words refer to things assigned by social convention.  The sacramentum (tantum)—sacrament only—water, bread and wine: accidents not in the substance.  In the Eucharist, body and blood (in the substance but not the accidents) are located between the sign and the signified(the effect of the sign).  Bread and wine: sign of.  Grace: signified.  Important: the relationship between the sign (body and blood) and the signified.  Augustine: when the word is added to the sign, that which is signified is signified.  The word makes the sacrament.  The sacrament is a visible sign of an invisible grace which affects the grace which it signifies.  This implies sacramental causality.  Augustine leaves ambigious the relation of the body and blood, and bread and wine.  Lindbeck: for Augustine, body an blood as well as bread and wine would be signs.  Body and blood signs of that which is life-giving.  Aquinas: the body and blood are themselves life-giving to body and soul.  Why did Augustine say that water and word affect grace if it is believed?  The belief is causally efficacisis in causing grace.  Aquinas cites this from Augustine to show that Augustine said that words as well as body and blood effectively cause grace.  Aquinas claimed that visible things can cause grace. Aquinas thought he was following Augustine.  But later, Calvin read Augustine in another way—that Augustine show body and blood as signs that do not in themselves cause grace as a life-giving efficacious cause.  The invisible grace is conferred by God directly.  According to Plato, divine reality as inward.  Augustine claimed that the sacraments are a reminder of that inward reality.  Aquinas claimed that the sign directly changes grace and is thus life-giving. 
The debate between Radbertus and Ratramnus was settled in the 1000’s in a controversy between Berangaruis and Lanfrane.  Berangaruis had read Augustine’s theory of signs, using Aristotle’s logic without the neo-Platonic view of Augustine.  The result was a memorialist interpretation of the Eucharist (a reminder of Jesus Christ).[4]  Without the neo-platonic element, ‘reminder’ is relatively empty.  In contrast was the Capernaite Herasy—physicalist (the body and blood of the historical Jesus in the Eucharist).  Radbertus in part.  After Berangaruis and Lafrane, the body was seen as the ascended body of Jesus.  Same as the historical Jesus but not physicalist. 
Transsubstantiation Doctrine: uses Aristotle’s substance (continues) and accidents (visible).  Substance is non-spacial, the center of physical reality, not visible.  Some accidents may not be visible, but they are not of the substance.  According to this doctrine, the substance changes at the consecration.  The body and blood are a sign of the inward grace which it causes.  Radbertus and Ratramnus both went back and forth on the physical presence of body and blood.  Accidents can refer to any attribute not essential to the substance.  Accidents are properties of substance.  Substance is necessarily essential to the substance.

1/29/93
Background to Anselm:
Liturgical penance.  Changes in liturgy gave rise to changes in piety (the way the biblical message is experienced and practiced).  Anselm was the first to grapple with the historical question: theological changes as a response to a change in experience.  Whereas Ratramnus and Radbertus lived in a period of transmission, Anselm lived in a period of assimilation (indiginization of Christianity).  There was a change in penance, especially between 877 and 1033 (the time of Anselm).  Penance had been rarely done—only for major scandals which affected the Church.  It had been a sacrament of reconciliation with the community.  Contrition (sorrow for sin) leading to confession (to the Church) leading to penance (may last for years) and absolution.  The purpose: supplying evidence that one who had injured society was sorry, so the society could readmit him.  In Ireland, a different pattern emerged.  Penance became more of a private matter, administered to individuals as a way of normal church discipline for minor as well as major sins.  Contrition leading to confession leading to absolution(declarative as distinct from the word from God which actually forgives sins) and penance (disciplinary, no longer to show society, and for satisfaction, paying compensation).  Is forgiveness in absolution even though still have to do penance?  Absolution—forgiveness of sin eternally.  No penalties in hell yet termporal penalties not forgiven.  Therefore, satisfaction becomes a substitute for temporal penalties.  The latter were more sincere before Anselm’s time.  This change worked out via piety rather than from a change in formal theology.  The cross makes up for our external penance.  Christ as the vindicator figure.  Only from around 950 was Christ seen as the victim.  A change in depiction.  Vindicator (king in victory) to victim.  This was reflected in the hymns as the victim depiction was salient through the middle ages.  How does this relate to the Eucharist?  From Rad and Rat to Anselm, the contents had changed.  Immortality-giving power of the Eurcharist (fount of immortality) during the Carolingian period) changed to the body and blood as the concentrated symbol (Mary Douglas) of Jesus on the cross (the Eucharist as the offering/sacrifice) during Anselm’s time.
Social/political changes:  After the Carolianian period, the dark middle ages began (late 800’s and 900’s).  Asiatic invaders from the East, Vikings from the North, and Muslims from the South.  What was rebuilt superficially by the Holy Roman Empire during the Carolianian period was destroyed.  A grass-roots recovery based on local power (power from below) then began.  Stronger economic and political power than during the Carolianian period.  By 1000, economic development had begun.  A warming climate, and an increasing population in Europe.  In intellectual matters, links to the past were severed.  So, no mindless copying.  Men sought instead to understand in new ways the old texts.    In the 1000’s, three of Aristotle’s treatices became increasingly available.  How to reason, how to find good premises, and how to detect logical errors.  This new terrain was learnt by the clergy.  Scientists learnt theology too.  A change from rhetorical to dialectical. Then, a change from monastic theology to scholastic theology.  The beginning of the separation of spirituality and theological writing.  This distinction remains to this day.  Rhetoric involves persuasion with a focus on the audience.  Dialectic is of demonstration, with a focus on the subject-matter.  Rhetoric emphasizes an appeal to the emotions (preaching) whereas dialectic emphasizes logic (math and the exact sciences).  These changes occurred during Anselm’s time. 

1/29/93: Discussion
Transubstantiation.  Substance: the subject.  Body and blood.  Accidents: predicate.   Substance is individualized (essense isn’t). 
Ratramus vs. Radburtus: 
They differ on whether Jesus’s historical body (his true body) is the body in the Eucharistist (figurative).Radburtus claims they are the same, as both are mystical(veritas), whereas Ratramus emphasizes the dissimilarity—Jesus’ historical body (veritas, or ‘true’, as the inward=outward) as distinct from the body in the Eucharist (figurative, as the inward does not equal the outward).  Truth: inward = outward; figure: inward differs from outward. 
Objective: change in body in the Eucharist occurs whether you are there or not.  Subjective: until you receive it, it isn’t the body (receptionist).  How do Ratramus and Radburtus fit in this dichotomy?

2/1/93
Anselm:
He is viewed as the best theologian between Augustine and Aquinus.  Knoll claims he transcends his age.
In the 1000’s, Anselm went to France from North Italy.  In terms of intellectual history, the monastic rhetorical and philosophical approach was then giving rise to the academic scholastic ‘dialogue’ theological approach.  Anselm was between these two; he had no division between philosophy and theology.  Ontological arguments for the existence of God went into his philosophy.  Anselm’s faith-seeking understanding (credo at intelligam—from Augustine), was to understand and intellectually contemplate that which one believes. 
Anselm’s ontological proof of God’s existence.  Three propositions.  First, the believer knows that God is such that a greater can not be thought.  Second, God exists only in my mind.  Third, a contradiction: God exists outside and within?  Therefore, God is not just inside.  He exists outside my mind.  If He is just inside, then He is not the greatest that can be thought.  Gaunilo was critical of this ‘proof’.  Karl Barth, on the other hand, claimed that this is a theological rather than a philosophical matter.  This is to make understanding a dialectic.  Augustine was less dialectically stringent; rather, he used contemplative intuition rather than an opposition.  Both Augustine and Anselm were seeking faith-seeking understanding. 
The Cur Dies Homo: Anselm, as archbishop at Canterbury, engaged in the theological dispute due to the increase in the Jewish population in Europe
Bozo studied at Laon and had dialogically worked out an argument against incarnation.
The problem: God created a perfect universe.  To harm it is infinitely serious. 
Anselm’s propostions:
  1. God willed a perfect universe; created humans for eternal blessedness.
  2. Such blessedness requires adherence to rightness/rectitude.
  3. Humans refused to do this, so we lost blessedness.
  4. No human can restore what has been lost.
  5. So in absence of an external aid, blessedness is lost.
Anselm was concerned with the species; individuals being of secondary importance.  God’s plan is frustrated by 3-5.  Man can’t restore himself, so some means outside of man is needed. 
Objections:
  1. The incarnation is infinitely shameful for God.
  2. If a less shameful way to redeem man, it would be rational for God to do it.
  3. God is rational. 
So, if the incarnation occurred, God is either foolish or powerless.
Anselm’s solution: satisfaction—perfect obedience.  Redemption must be a satisfaction which is equal or more to the sin.  Something must be added which is more than the loss of the sin.  So, perfect obedience is necessary.  So the incarnation was necessary.  As alternatives, unconditional forgiveness.  But this rewards evil.  Or punishment.  Order would be reestablished.  But, total good would be less.  So there must be satisfaction—something more than making up for the loss of sin.  Man ought to perform the satisfaction, but we can’t because we are finite sinful beings.  We owed perfect obedience beforehand.  Satisfaction is needed to ‘pay’ God for the injury suffered.  Perfect obedience from man isn’t enough.  Only the god-man can and ought to do it.
The incarnation makes up for sin, but does not give satisfaction (payment to God for the injury done).  Jesus Christ paid our satisfaction. 

2/3/93
Anselm’s dialectical necessity of Deus Homo: The God-Man.  It is necessary, given the logical argument made by Anselm.  It is a conditional argument: if God is just, merciful, and created a perfect universe with a species of free creatures.  If they fall, then the incarnation is necessary.  A necessity compatible with God’s freedom, so it is not a constraint on God.   Two kinds of questions can be raised.  Is the argument internally coherent?  Are his premises correct?  Consider whether there are alternatives that discplace the necessity as well as or better than Anselm. 
Anselm’s rhetorical picturing of Deus Homo.  Anselm uses the metaphor of a painted background.  A moziac.  Central biblical parts are indispensable (e.g. the passion  story), and while others are not.   These others include the virgin birth, Augustine’s claim that humans were created to replace the fallen angels (Anselm: humans were created for their own sake and are not necessary for the painting), and culturally attractive imagery such as feudalism. 
Honor held feudal society together.  Rights, duties and privileges were salient.  Everyone, even surfs, had honor, which was violated if any party did not assume their duties.  When God’s honor is violated, order and beauty of the universe in relation to the creator is violated.  Lindbeck: Anselm’s honor issue is not necessary to his argument. 
Alternatives to Anselm’s Satisfaction-Incarnation argument: The ransom theory which Bernard uses.  Or understanding salvation as divination.  The human problem is mortality rather than sin.  Salvation is immortality, to become divine though not God.  Human nature divinized. The West, using legalistic rather than ontological terms, didn’t buy into this view for awhile. Legalistic: sin as like breaking the law. Also, the West was platonic: human nature as a single entity or whole. Platonic realism: all universals are universals. Their full reality is in the idea.  Christian theology: the idea of God.  Humans participate in the idea of the human.  In contrast, 1) moderate realism (Aristotle): common human nature is within humans. Yet, no humanity outside of us in an idea, and 2) nominalism (conceptualism): positivist, and the idea that all we are is individual humans (we share a common name).  Western thought is not as platonic as Anselm.     Anselm: via incarnation, humans are divinized. This really didn’t take hold in the West.  Lindbeck: could one see the problem as sin and come up with a different notion of salvation, not necessarily divination.  Key: the analysis of the problem and the support need to be consistent. 

Abelard had a moral influence theory for the atonement and incarnation.  He agreed with Bozo against the ransom theory.  So not logical (i.e. inconsistent with other premises of God) to think of the devil having rights over men who have sinned; that God must break this right by the incarnation (the devil gets caught).  1 Cor 4:6-7: the powers of the world would  not have crucified Jesus had they known who he was.  Abelard does not distinguish between punishment and satisfaction.  He concludes that Jesus is punished for us according to Anselm’s account.  Abelard rejects the penal substitution theory which he thinks Anselm is arguing.  So Abelard is not really rejecting Anselm’s account, as satisfaction does not imply punishment.  Like Anselm, Abelard was influenced by a cross-centered piety.  The transforming love from Jesus’ death forgives our sins.  Abelard’s understanding of the atonement as well as the incarnation.  But what about an angel as an alternative?  And what happens to sins not forgiven?  Also, what if the universe was not made perfect?  Pelagius: our action—it is necessary for us to respond in love.  Abelard: God gives us this love to respond.  Lindbeck: but this creates problems.
According to Abelard, it is one’s duty to follow one’s conscience, even when it is wrong.  We have impulses to do what we think is wrong.  The impulses are not sin; rather, one’s consent to them is sin.  Key: whether they result in action.  Original sin: impulses not in themselves sinful.  So if Jesus had not been crucified, then the crucifiers would have sinned in not following their consciences. This plays into semi-Plagianism: it is up to us whether we consent or not. 

Sic et Non (yes and no).  The application of dialectic to a new area of thought (to the authorities of the faith).  Abelard has 158 questions on many topics.  He cites authorities on both sides, identifying conflicts in the sources.  He looks at their contexts (translation errors, how language is used).  Then, a residue of contradiction, weighing authorities by reputation and reason.  This was the beginning of modern historical criticism.  Also, the influence of ‘yes and no’ on how Aquinas sets up his questions—a thesis in the middle of each article.  First, objections, then responses (argument for the thesis), then answers to the objections.  Western theologians, like Abelard, expect to find problems with statements of authorities.  Eastern theologians assume that everyone basically in agreement.

2/5/93
Anselm died in 1109.  Abelard: 1079-1142.  Bernard: 1090-1154.

Bernard:
He saw Abelard as having plagian pride.  He saw Abelard’s moral influence theory as insufficient because it depends upon something we do—our response to Jesus.  Initiative and responsibility seem to be left up to humans.  Bernard stressed the prevenience of God.  Self-righteous humans are the worst kind.  Humility was stressed by Bernard.  In this sense, Bernard is Augustinian.  Bernard was a monastic reformer and a spiritual guide.  He was indifferent to logic (e.g. as used by Anselm and Abelard).  He saw it as in contrast to spirituality.  Bernard did not reject Abelard’s language (e.g. that Christ saves by his act of love).  Like Abelard, Bernard believed that what Christ did more than makes up for the evil in the universe.  To Bernard, atonement is a ransom paid to the devil.  A fish-hook to trick the devil in the struggle between God and the devil.  Jesus as the hero-warrior-mediator, defeating the devil.  Not until the 1200’s did Bernard’s ransom theory lose influence.  Jesus as victor.  Luther would pick up on this.  Similar to Bernard, Anselm saw Adam and Eve as traitors but Jesus triumphed.  Lindbeck: Anselm’s theory was less adapted to feudalism.  Anselm did not depend upon his own culture.  This could explain the influence of him beyond his age.  Unlike feudal culture, Anselm’s basic pattern was not triangular (God, devil, humans).  Rather, God and humans.  Humans deal directly with God, humans being for the Fall, rather than having been seduced by the enemy.  Abelard too has two main actors (God and humans), though unlike Anselm humanity’s role is central (as no price is being paid; rather, in atonement one finds love solo gratia).     In Bernard’s ransom theory, in contrast, there are three main actors.  

2/5/93: Discussion
Anselm does not discuss original sin.  It is a presupposition to the argument rather than a premise.  Is it necessary for his argument?  Anselm’s focus is on how God’s honor has been defiled.  In this sense, Anselm is in line with that which is salient in the feudal culture (honor).  It is necessary that Jesus dies to give satisfaction.  He was sinless and didn’t have to die.  It was his choice.
Anselm had two audiences:
The non-Christian.  His purpose was not to convert; rather, it was to remove obstacles to faith.  Theists, such as Jews and Muslims, were steeped in logic yet didn’t accept the incarnation.  So Anselm focused on the incarnation rather than the issue of God which he assumed had been already agreed to. 
The Christian.  Anselm wants Christians to more fully enjoy their faith, via understanding what they believe.  The logic of faith was beautiful to Anselm.  His aim of mankind: to enjoy God; perfect obedience.  This is just.  Theology is the beginning of blessedness.  The starting point is the blessingness of God.  The loss of perfection is the starting point.  The Fall is the disorder in the universe.  Disorder is more important than is sin.  If this disorder is not corrected, God would be frustrated.  But this can’t be as it is not in God’s nature, so there must be a correction.  It is necessary to restore order that there be satisfaction through a God-man. 
In a nutshell, Anselm is concerned about the problem of justice and the mercy of God.  Atonement is necessary and Jesus did not die in necessity.  Why satisfaction? Why not forgiveness or punishment?  Forgiveness would not be just; evil would have the same status as good.  And punishment lowers the net-good, and would not restore the order of the universe.  Satisfaction: only God is able to make it, but only man’s responsibility.  The God-man is necessary. 
God is faithful to himself; he is not bound to necessity.  Anselm claims that mercy doesn’t work when incongruent with justice.  Satisfaction fills in the hole plus it makes up for not having honored God when we should have done so.  It all goes back to ORDER: mercy can’t be unjust.  Satifaction relates justice and mercy such that order is restored.  It maintains honor in the ordering of things. 
According to Forde, the resurrection doesn’t seem necessary for Anselm.  The cross leads to sacrifice which provides the satisfaction.  Does God have to be satisfied?  What about God’s mercy and love?  According to Forde, “Jesus himself, though he might have and quite possibly did reckon with a violent death…, seems not to have understood or interpreted his own death as a sacrifice for others or ransom for sin.”  If so, then Anselm’s view of vicarious satisfaction finds little support in the scripture.  Scripture never speaks of God as one who has to be satisfied or propitiated before being merciful or forgiving.  Since Jesus voluntarily gave  himself up to death, he gave more than was required.[5]  To Forde, “God must die and be raised.  The ‘must’…is not the abstract and a priori ‘must’ of a rational or legal scheme, but an a posteriori reflection of the mercy actually given.”  To Forde, there are three problems with Anselm:
  1. How could Christ’s death be necessary and at the same time be a free and voluntary sacrifice?
  2. Equivolence between Jesus’ death and the demand of the divine honor not demonstrated.  But, a logical fallacy: worth assumed.  So equivelence can’t be demonstrated; you can’t prove the worth of something by asking how great an evil it would be to destroy it.  Anselm: the evil of destroying Jesus is greater than the evil of allowing the human race to be destroyed.  So Jesus’ life was worth more than that of all humans’ sin. 
  3. Justice above mercy.  But, if God gets satisfaction, where is mercy at all? Mercy against justice is wrong?
Anselm provides an account to explain why God would let Jesus suffer unless He had to.  But is Anselm’s explanation too much a legalistic rationalization which oversimplifies the human problem? 

2/15/93

‘The Aristitilian Invasion’: the 1200’s
Transformations in Western Europe; changes accelerated in the 1100’s.  For instance, educational systems: a university was created(Balonia, in Italy, was established in 1150; the University of Paris in 1205), and the amount of learning expanded.  The logic of Aristotle had been translated, followed by his other works.  Legal learning became more accessible, and the writings of medicine were translated.  Specialization became necessary: faculties of arts, law, medicine, and theology.  Initially, this knowledge came via Spain and the Muslim schools.  Aristotle’s texts were accompanied by commentaries.  For instance, Averroes, in Spain, and Avicenna from central Asia.  These were Arab thinkers.  The initial wave of latin thought came via Averroes.  He had been influenced by neo-platonism, an Aristotilian way of thinking, and a pantheistic world-view (deterministic). 
To Aristotle, ‘nous’ is the highest intellect principle.  The supreme nous (thought thinking about itself) is the highest kind of activity.  Pure actuality (no change); not changed by temporal change.  The unmoved mover.  It is a focus for desire.  All activities aspire to it.  Nous moves everything else to it, but is itself unmoving.  Averroes combined this with Platonist thinking.  The Neo-platonist ideal was ‘the one’: cascades of light moving to a non-extended light; everything goes from it, becoming more and more fragmented as it gets further and further away.  To Averroe, the one is nous.  So, not oneness; rather, intelligence that creates reality by radiating outward.  Aristotle taught that the agent intellect is one in all humans.  It is the power that abstracts forms from matter.  When thinking in the abstract, one gets pure intelligibles such that everyone’s ideas are the same.  For instance, 2+2=4.  No temporal, cultural or individual conditioning once it is achieved.  These pure things always exist in things (Plato: apart from things).  One agent intellect in the Universe. We think of abstract universals to the extent we participate in this one mind (monopsychism).  The one agent intellect is from, not in, God.  So, the higher one searches for knowledge, the less of an individual one is.  At death, one’s mind joins with the one agent intellect.  This is to deny individual immortality and individual free-will. 
Other changes in the 1200’s included the emergence of castles and gothic cathedrals.  Also, the crusades (four) were in that century.  Trade was stimulated, and cities grew.  Marco Polo lived then, for instance.
For theology, there was a new kind of religious order.  The growth of cities stressed the parish system, and monestaries were too remote to help.   So the Dominicans and Fransicians were established to serve the urban poor.  The Dominicans emphasized education (against heresies). 
At the fourth Laterin Council at 1215, transubstantiation was accepted, and confession was made mandatory at least once per year.  Trial by ordeal under the church was no longer ok.  For instance, someone suspected to be a heretic could no longer be thrown in blessed water to see if they sink.  So, a fight against magic. 
This period was more rational than was the late middle ages.  Recall that the late 1600’s included the Salem witch trials. 
Averroism was a threat to Christianity.  Students learned it at the universities, where Aristotle’s material was primary.  Theology was for the elite (not all the clergy).  The Arts and Sciences was Averroism.  Most of the educated clergy studied it, so the church authorities turned to the new orders for help.  At the University of Paris in the mid 1200’s, Aquinus (a Franciscian) christianized Aristotle (rather than Plato, as Augustine had done. So Aquinas represented a radical break from early Christian theology..  He was widely attacked.  Aquinas was born in 1225 and died fifty years later.  In 1277, Archbishop Tempier condemned some of Aquinas’ teaching.  So, there were tensions between the prevailing Platonist Christianity and Aquinas’ Aristotilian Christianity.

2/17/93
Aquinas(1225-1275):
His philosophy ws incidental to his theological task.  He used Aristotle rather than Plato.
The ontological contrast between Plato and Aristotle: Are forms (universals) antecedent to the concrete thing (ante reim)?  Plato: yes.  Universal form is transcendent.  To Christian Platonists, universal forms exist in the mind of God.  Aristotle: no.  Nominalist: no.  Are the forms imminent in the particulars (in re)?    Plato: yes.  Aristotle: yes (an individualized, so only potentially universal).  Nominalist: no.  Are forms after the thing, in minds (post rem)?  Plato: yes.  Aristotle: yes: potential universalizability becomes actual when in human minds, yet not perfectly so.  Fully actual only in God’s mind.  So we exist more fully in the mind of God.   Nominalist: yes.  We form universal concepts so that as concepts, rather than real things, exist universally in the mind. 
Plato’s ideas originated in math.  He saw how abstract mathematical structures are in concrete things.  Mathematical reality seems like it is out there to be discovered.  To Aristotle, the form of circularity is present to some degree in concrete realities and in minds, but not having independent existence.  To the nominalist, circularity is a form which humans invent. 
Epistemology: how one comes to know.  Plato: know by turning inward and upward, away from sensory experience.  To Aristotle, all knowledge is from sensory experience, from which we abstract the universals; some things can only be known by inference.  The proper object of the mind is the essence of material things.  So, turn toward sensory experience. 
In sum, for Plato reality: forms are out there.  For Aristotle, reality: forms are in sensible things.  Plato is thus more favorable to the mystical.  For Aquinas, mystical experience (direct intuitive knowledge of the divine) is an unpredictable gift from God.  It is not strived for. 
Human Nature:
Aristotle: The soul: the substantial form of the body.  No soul without a body. The form of the fetus becomes a human sould when it develops to a certain point.  So Aristotle denied the immortal life of the soul.  Due to having reason (an immaterial grasping an immaterial reality), the soul can exist without a body.  Separated souls are not persons.  He accounts for the resurrection; Plato doesn’t.
Plato: The soul: reality beyond the body, taken up by bodies.  Soul and body are two separate substances.

Augustine saw theology as a practical science, whereas Aquinas saw it as primarily speculative, as it considers truth.  Philosophy is within theology only in giving probably support.  So, arguments about God are theologically only probable arguments. Only scripture is of God necessarily.  Faith may be enhanced by reasoning, however.  If one uses reason to find faith, then faith suffers. 

2/19/93: Discussion
Aquina’s arguments:  he first considers objections, then cites an authority (sed contra), then gives a reply (responsio). 
Aquinus argued that if God is truth, then correct reason could not contradict revelation.  Reason can error; revelation can’t.  So revelation is superior. 
On the existence of God: whether God exists.  Aquinas uses reason (proof), yet he had also claimed that revelation is superior.  Proof: 5 ways.  1-3: defining the term ‘God’.  4-5: qualitative proofs.  Closer to the Christian view of God.  Is this proof?  Given, only sure knowledge is from revelation, the five proofs are demonstrations of revelations.  Aquinas didn’t intend the proofs as proofs.  Arguments from reason have probable weight.  Faith we have; revelation is from God.  Faith is a theological virtue.  Faith is belief and assent.  Evil is belief without assent.  Will (assent) and intellect (belief).  Two sorts of faith: formed and unformed.  Only faith formed by charity (will) is virtuous.  Otherwise, it is just belief.  Luther: faith alone.  But, Aquinas didn’t talk of justification.  Charity without faith is loving something other than God.  So faith must be prior.  Faith gives content to what is loved. 
Aquinas sees all things as being directed to God. The Summa is about this.  His theology is directed toward the beginning of heaven in us now; our end in God.  Augustine is more concerned with sin and redemption.  To Aquinas, God is perfect and primary.  Aquinas was using Augustine here.  His Platonism forms the basis for the orientation of the Summa.  Constructs on it use Aristotle.  Platonism expresses the end.  Aristotle used in the means to the end.  This gives Aquinas balance.

2/24/93
Aristotle’s causes(e.g. of a chair):
Formal: shape (it’s nature)
Material: wood (what it is made of)
Efficient: the builder (something that pushes something else)
Final: to sit on (the purpose or function of)

Faith vs. Reason; revealed theology vs. natural philosophy (formal v. material causes)
For instance, A book.  Several formalities of: can be thrown, read, smelled.  A human.  Several formalities of: as chemicals, or for whom Jesus died.  So the same material object can be known in different ways.
There is a formal distinction between theology and philosophy.  Material: different domains/classes of objects. They can be known by theology(faith) or philosophy(reason). Like two circles with a little bit in common.  The trinity and incarnation can be known only by faith (God as the redeemer of the world and the goal of human longing) and the sensible world only by reason (though it can include inferences from theology (God as the first cause—as a preamble).  Aquinas: natural theology, as a preamble, serves as a foundation for the formal relation between reason and faith.  No longer a material distinction; rather, a formal distinction.  Preambles can be known by reason as well as by faith.  For instance, on the circularity of the earth, faith doesn’t displace reason.  Faith knows about the material world, the preamble, and the trinity/incarnation.  Reason knows about the material world and the preamble.  From faith, reason can give demonstrations (rather than probable knowledge) of preambles.  Theology takes scripture as its first premise.  Reason doesn’t displace faith.  If one knows philosophically that God exists, one still needs faith to believe because of different formal causes.  So, if a material distinction between theology and philosophy, reason displaces faith.  If a formal distinction, reason does not displace it.  The will moves the intellect when the will is attracted to a truth of which the will knows in revelation.  First, love of the truth (revealed), then movement of the will, then assent of the intellect.  So reason within theology(faith) to clarify what is believed and to answer objections to the faith. From the point of view of theology, one does not come to faith by reason, ,rather than via love (which then moves the intellect). 
God is not directly knowable.  Because of Atheists, God is not self-evident.  Also, God is not self-evident because knowledge starts with sense experience.  This is so (indirectness of knowing God) from the point of view of theology as well as philosophy (indirectly via faith as well as reason).  So, Aquinas gives an ontological argument of God.  Philosophical demonstrations from theology: probabilistic knowledge of scripture.  Within theology, there are five probable arguments of faith for the existence of God. 
All our knowledge of God is by analogy.  So it has a negative aspect—what God is not.  From two directions.  By negative perfections (said of God by denying): infinite, immutable, one.  God is not limited yet also transcended.  Probable arguments for that which is known/revealed already by faith.  Second, there are positive attributes of God (yet includes negations): intelligent, will, love.  Both ways are removing imperfections of God and affirming qualities; saying what God is not. 

2/26/93
Based on Aristotle:
Ipsum esse (to be itself) is the first cause, operating on the 2nd causes, the act (necessarily or freely) to change (move) something from state x to y. 
Based on Plato (the traditional view):
God as the unity and purpose of all perfections.  Aquinas did not disagree with this, but thought that a model based on Aristotle would be better.  Plato: ideas as ideational. To Artistotle, ideas as activity: thought thinking of itself.  Aquinas:  the act of existence as an act in and of itself.  Esse: real; Essentia: the essence. Aquinas distinguishes these two. Does it exist, of the former; What is it, of the latter.  Two separate questions. To exist is an act distinguishable from descriptions of what something is.  To Aquinas, the first cause is: to be itself.  God is existence—an infinite sea of being.  God is revealed; God is: to be itself (ipsum esse).  The first cause confers existence onto everything.  The second cause is the essence (which is based on ipsum esse). 
God is the total cause and yet the creatures, on the level of essence, have freedom.  So God is the total cause, whether we have free-will or not.  God as the first cause is radically different from the second cause.  Talking about God is analogical rather than equivocal or univocal.  Aquinas gives examples of analogical terms (eg. Healthy).  Analogy signifies different relations to one and the same thing.  Lindbeck’s examples: the river flows; time flows.  ‘flow’ is here used analogically.  Also, ‘see’ can be used mentally as well as physically.  We know something of the two realities as there is other information  on both.  But with God, this ‘info’ is missing.  Consider the difference between significatum (that which is signified—which is affirmed in the case of God) and modus significandi (the mode of signifying—which is not affirmed in the case of God).  So you can’t make words describing God informative.  What we say about God tells us nothing of what is in God (ipsum esse).  But, we can understand how things are related to God.

 2/26/93: Discussion
Two types of grace:
  1. Habitual.  Infused grace.  Habitual injection of grace, restoring freedom of the will which was lost in the Fall. The Fall maes it impossible for us to turn to God alone.  Grace is needed to establish the possibility.
  2. The grace that sustains us.

According to Lindbeck, Aquinas on atonement has some differences from Anselm’s view that mercy is not inconsistent with Justice (punishment and satisfaction is just). 
The capacity to do good is due to grace which is given to all.  Some say yes, some say no.  Augustine, in contrast, maintained that grace is only given to the elect.  Aquinas believes in predestination but not in an elect.   Aquinas assumed that all were baptized.  This was by in large true in his day.  Predestination was a separate issue from that of grace. Aquinas: those who are damned are lost because they have freely sinned even though they had been given grace.  So, not universal salvation even though everyone gets grace.  Aquinas sees ‘choice’ in a sea of grace.  The more powerfully God acts, the freer we are.  Grace gives us the power to be what we can be (free).  The doctrine of original sin isn’t the culprit behind the idea that many people are in hell.  Strict moral plageans put more people in hell than did those of solo gratia.  The Western church has put an emphasis on sin; the Eastern church has put an emphasis on death.  The eastern church is platonic: Because of the incarnation, humanity changed—became divinized.  Implication: universal salvation.  In contrast, the western church has emphasized the cross.
Statements from Aquinas (Summa T.):
Q. 20, art. 1: “actions of will or appetite which refer to good are bound to be naturally prior to those which refer to evil” and “that which is more universal is naturally prior”. 
Q. 2, art. 3: “that which has the greatest truth is also greatest in being”
Q. 16, art. 1: “truth consists in conformity between an intellect and a thing”
Q. 21, art. 4: “when God acts mercifully, he does not do what is contrary to his justice, but does more than his justice requires”[6]
Q. 22 Art. 1: “God in his abundant goodness bestows what is owing to a creature more liberally than its relative status deserves”
Q. 22, art. 2: providence is “the reason for the ordination of things to their end” “Every agent acts for the sake of an end. 
Q. 23, art. 1: Predestination is “the reason why a rational creature is brought to eternal life”.
To love is to will good for someone (IQ. 26, arts2-3), the reason why man inclines to virtue is that he is rational.  To act virtuously is to act in accordance with reason.
“The loss of original justice has the character of punishment. Death and all attendent defects of the body are therefore the punishments of original sin.” (II ae, 85, 5 resp).
The form of man, his rational soul, isn’t entirely dependent on corporeal matter (1-II ae, 85, 6).
“Nor can the debt of punishment be forgiven save by God alone, against whom the offence is committed, and who is the judge of men (II ae, Q.109, art 8, resp).
Sin is falling short of what befits one’s nature (I-II, Q. 109, a8).

3/1/93

Philosophy, or natural theology, provides probable support for faith. From the standpoint of revealed theology(e.g.predestination, sin, grace, justification, merit, and hope), however, philosophy provides tools rather than probable support.   Aquinas was the first wave of Aristotilian philosophy in theology.  Aquinas uses Augustine’s Christian Platonism in his affirmations.  But, he uses Aristotle’s categories.  Unlike Augustine, Aquinas starts with God as omnicausal (the first cause), with creatures’ free-will as the second cause, making up the total cause.  Not two finite causes, such as two men pulling a baige along a canal wherein only one is necessary.  Rather, God is necessary as the first cause whether we act or not.  So the first and second cause can each be the total cause.  To Augustine, sin is the reason for our total helplessness.  To Aquinas, we are totally helpless not only because we sin but because we are natural creatures. 
Grace, to Aquinas, is a disposition given by God, as the favor of God and the gift of God.  Uncreated grace is primary while uncreated grace, or the disposition to the good, is secondary.  Aquinus emphasizes this distinction whereas Augustine does not make it.  The analysis of grace as uncreated and created has an Aristotilian basis.  Created grace depends on uncreated grace.  The preparation for grace is itself dependent on grace. Grace is before anything we do.  Prevenience of grace. The infusion of grace changes the direction of our being.  Transformation of self, then God forgives and accepts us.  A transformational model.  From the view of humans, the order is reversed.  Forgiveness first (resembles the forensic model).  People may think they have grace when they don’t. Aristotle claimed that we have knowledge of what is inside of us from sensory experience.  So we do not have certain knowledge of being saved.  To Aquinas, faith, love, and hope are necessary.  Hope has certainty—it is to be certain of God’s goodness. 

3/5/93: Discussion
Worship is only to God, whereas veneration includes giving honor to holy people (nothing is being asked for; asking the saints to pray with one).  Mary is honored by Catholics because she was obedient to God. This was not meritorious, as it is what would be expected.
Hoeck and Gansfort: the issue with regard to indulgences was authority.  Getting out of purgatory (not hell) is conditional on contributions. The authority of scripture is above that of tradition. Oberman interprets Hoeck and Gansfort as two traditions.  An authoritarian oral tradition with written tradition.  Not distinct; two sources of tradition (the church fixes scripture into canon—the church’s appropriation of scripture, a communal thing, was key).  There is also the authority of scripture and the church.  To Oberman, there is continuity between Augustine and the reformers in a spectrum.  So the change in the reformation has not been as much as we have thought.  Vincent of Lerins interprets catholocism as what is everywhere, by all people and at all times believed (the Christian lowest common denominator). 
Three great splits in Christianity: Church v. Synagogue, East v. West, Protestant v. Catholic. 
Purgatory:
Catherine of Genoa viewed purgatory as an experience like one she had had—experience of a mystical union, of being purified and of desiring God.  So the key is the soul’s transaction with God.  Purgatory as terrible temporary torment to purify one’s soul.  A far less pain than there would be if one were to be separated from God.  Purgatory includes a longing for God, yet separated by sin experienced as pain, yet there is also joy. 

3/5/93
1300-1500:
1500’s represented a break with the past, shown in the Rennasance and the Reformation.  The climate had turned bad for agriculture (famines) in the 1300-1500 period.  A decline in the population of Western Europe.  In religion, clinging to old patterns, even when dysfunction because it was not known how to replace them.  No new monastic orders.  An increase in church corruption, even as there was an increase in literacy.  In general, there were increasing divisions and pluralism in society, with the lack of a unifying vision.  But, there were advances too.  Logic advanced, as did technology (glasses, clocks, and navigation).  Popular piety, Christian faith at the personal level, was increasing.  Pilgrimages, cults of saints and Mary, and indulgences.  Theology was done in academia rather than in monestaries.  It was not tied to the political, economic, and social contexts.  There was a call for reform ‘in head and members’.  The Condemnation of 1277, against Latin Avaroism (use of Aristotle in Latin Theology—e.g. Aquinas), influenced university theology.  This theology emphasized freedom of God as well as humans, being anti-determinism.  The potentia absoluta (absolute power of God) was emphasized.  Freedom over that of self.  Contradictory, so logic was used.  Led to speculations which themselves led to later scientific advances.  The potentia ordmata (the ordaining freedom of God): necessity leading to God’s freedom and human freedom.  This fit with nominalism and was against Latin Avarroism.   The analogically intelligible moderate realism (aristotilian) was replaced by nominalistic univocity (breaking reality into parts via logic—an atomistic view of reality).  So universals not in reality but in the mind as concepts (conceptualist and terminist).  For instance, Ockham (1349) was nominalist in name only.  Emphasis on freedom.  Reality as atomistic facts, sorted out by God in His freedom.  Platonic: God as the total of the universals.  Via Moderna Nominalist dominated universities.  Other schools, such as Vix Antique (Scotist and Thomist) were influence by the above. 

3/22/93
Late Medieval: 1500’s
Doctrinal turmoil.  Trends went toward reform as well as Catholocism.  An issue was authority: how does a tradition reach decisions about what is a doctrine?  Oberman: scripture is materially but not formally sufficient.  ‘Tradition One’.  One can find implicit as well as explicit things in scripture.  Or, one could see two sources of authoritative revelation: oral tradition (can suppliment scripture) and scripture (not materially sufficient but can play a decisive role).  ‘Tradition Two’.  Practices not verbally articulated can be within ‘tradition’.  Scripture read from a particular form of worship.  Human vs divine traditions.  The church’s interpretation of scripture (eg. The credo, the trinity), as a divine tradition. Do the creeds simply interpret scriptures or is it creative interpretation in a way that scripture itself doesn’t include?  Mainline reformers and Medieval Church saw such creeds as coming from scripture.   The Catholic Church held that they were authoritative interpretations of scripture. Reformers maintained that they were summaries of scripture.  Neither the Catholic Church nor the early (1600’s) reformers saw interpretation as an individual matter. 
Tradition one: scripture not formally sufficient.  Issue: did the church’s interpretation authentically summarize scripture, or did it go beyond scripture via the guidance of the holy spirit?  This issue was not raised in the late Middle Ages.  How one goes about authoritatively interpreting scripture went unclarified.  Rather, emphasis was on freedom (e.g. Thomists, Sartists, and Nominalists).  The universe as a ‘heap of facts’ ordered by an external will of God.  So ont just one order possible.  In the late Middle Ages, the universe was seen as not necessarily ordered in a hierarchical order. 
Grace and Glory:
Scotus saw no necessary relationship between grace and glory.  Grace as not necessarily a prerequisite for glory.  Created grace was no longer seen as the indwelling of the holy spirit; rather, uncreated grace as the indwelling of the holy spirit, but it was downplayed.  A polarization between grace and freedom: divine and human causation.  In the 1200’s (e.g. Aquinas), sola gratia tended to treate humans as passive in the process of justification.  God as the sole actor.  Those believing in human freedom denied the prevenience of grace, seeing humans as part of the cause of justification.  Augustine’s view of God as the total first cause and humans as the total free cause was not upheld in the late middle ages.  Augustine held that God predestines us to salvation. All that is left is double-predestination or semi-plagianism. 

3/23/93
Developments in the late middle ages:
The infused grace-glory relation, still unclear, was seen then as a contract.  The reward of glory is not merited, but is given by God.  Earlier, it was seen as an intrinsic relationship.  Second, a growing influence of human contribution.  God and man—each a partial cause.  Recall that the traditional Augustianian view was that God was either the sole cause(Augustine) or all-cause(Aquinas and Augustine). 
Quod in se facere: ‘to do what is in one’.  If done, god won’t deny grace.  So, denies prevenient grace.  Emphasis on human initiative.  Reconcilable with Augustine’s view of God’s freedom.  Augustine: God’s ordination freely of glory.  Human effort after grace is given.  In the late middle ages, however, human effort too.  ‘Neo-plagenian’.  Pentence was emphasized in the liturgy.  Issue: how does a fallen baptized Christian become justified and sanctified?  How does one know?  The proper practice of pentance.  A shift from baptism/eucharist to eucharist(Anselm), to pentence.  An anxiety over the question of the forgiveness of sins led to introspective self-examination, with motives included and the proper attitude.  Previously, contrition (sorrow for sins out of love of God—i.e. Aquinas).  Late middle ages: attrition--servile fear of punishment was sufficient, fitting with the idea that we do what we can.  Biel was a neo-plagean.  He was on the eve of the Reformation.  A contritionist and a late nominalist.  Kolde (1480), influenced by Biel, focused on preparation for confession.  To him, contrition meant one was capable of doing it from one’s own natural power, there being sufficient free-will for this to be possible.  Luther: such contrition is so hard that he felt he would hate God.  So Luther had a terror of conscience. 
Attritionists:
John of Paltz, an Augustinian (as was Luther), argued that God was not so strict.  Luther: this could lead to the lost soul.  Luther was not a lax attritionist; he did not want to ease up on himself.  Bradwardine—Occum of Fiori, another attritionist, felt that being freely sorry is enough.  Luther’s solution was powerful in Europe, so others had been suffering from terrified consciences. 
The neo-plagean problem was not pride.  Anxiety over salvation had been pride.  The solution had been sola gratia.  The neo-plageans felt that a little free-will was also necessary.  This was not the same thing as pride.  Luther felt the problem was neo-plageanism and the promise of salvation.  The problem was no longer pride.  Recall that in the late middle ages, pentence was important—the forgiveness of guilt was salient.  Penalties were thought to be not only temporal but in purgatory as well.  Indulgences and purgatory were salient at the time.  Prayers for the dead were for those who had died yet not yet purged by the discipline of satisfactions but were destined for heaven.  This was influenced by a clarified notion of purgatory and of indulgences which were used for the remission of pentences.  Sufferage of the church for the remission of the satisfactions.  Key was the jurisdictional right of the church.  In the 95 Theses, was Luther attacking the doctrine of indulgences (as prayer speeding up the process of purgation)?  Does Catherine of Seana’s understanding of purgatory oppose Luther’s opposition in his theses?  Lindbeck: No.  Therefore, Luther was against only the abuses of indulgences rather than against the theology behind them.
In the Heenburg dispute of 1518, the emphasis was on humility (the importance of faith formed by humility).  In 1519, a different kind of answer by Luther.  A different structure than in 1518.

3/26/93
Reformers saw two problems: neoplagianism and the certainty of salvation. Reformers such as Luther used Augustine, who had stressed the human inability to contribute to his or her own salvation, sola prevenient grace, and the sinful nature of mankind.  But, neo-plagianism was not that opposed to Augustine, as it was a penitential kind.  The terrified conscience.  The sola gratia was silent on this.  Luther studied scripture, guided by Augustine.  By 1517-18 (Heidelburg), Luther had made progress on answering the problem of the terrified conscience.  In 1545, Luther wrote on God’s righteousness, as being an active, punishment, attribute of God.  God’s righteousness is in Paul (Romans 1:17).  It is by His righteousness that He justifies us. Some relation to faith.  By the time of Heidelburg, Luther had come up with Justification by Faith.  Luther understood faith as infused—a subjective disposition formed by humility.  Faith of recognition of one’s sins.  This is what is justified.  Faith which lives the life of the cross; a precondition for forgiveness. 
Pre-reform views of justification:
The Transformative Model: transformation (via infused grace) leads to forgiveness/justification (conditional).
The Forensic Model: Unconditional justification/forgiveness leads to sanctification, with good actions as spontaneous fruits.  God’s judicial declaration of righteousness, the promise of forgiveness imputing alien righteousness via performative language(e.g. like marriage, the language describes the union between God and the soul at the beginning of the transformation).  Christ’s righteousness belongs to us; our sins are assumed by Christ. The ‘blessed exchange’.  An alien righteousness comes into us via the word of promise and forgiveness.  Christ is the actor.  The inwardly free Lord and the servant.  Sola fide.  Luther held this view.
To Luther, justification is the dialogue between sinner and God.  Faith, to Luther, is the reception of the first righteousness by trust (fiducia), secondarily by assent (assensus).  Before the reformers, the assent was emphasized.  To Luther, God alone justifies.  It is God’s promise: forgiveness in Jesus Christ, the object of faith.  God may really change us, but this is not what justifies us. 
It is by grace alone, through the work of the Holy Spirit, that one receives faith (sola gratia).  How is it assured?  Not trusting one’s own faith; rather, it is the certainty in God’s declaration/promise in Jesus Christ. So it is in looking outward, rather than inward into one’s self. 
Augustine held the transformative model, as from God’s point of view.  Aquinas held the forensic model, as from the sinner’s perspective.  Luther agreed that theology should be done from the sinner’s view (coram deo).  Not from an objective, detached, point of view. Whereas Aquinas took a sapientiel point of view (the doxilatical point of view), Luther took an existential point of view.  To Luther, the assurance of salvation depends on God, not the self.  To Aquinas, hope is as certainty because of God.  Therefore, pre-reform had room for the reform’s solution to the problem of the certainty of salvation was not discovered until modern times under hope (Aquinas) and faith (Luther).

3/26/93: Discussion
Luther was against the emphasis on the goodness of the religious life.  He thought few are actually called.  The fact that it was a prevalent social practice, laxity in them due to those who were in it who weren’t really called.  He gives validity to non-religious life.  Luther didn’t think the Church had gone astray, although Calvin did.
The righteousness imputed to us is alien, from the cross (God’s righteousness) precedes ‘proper’ righteousness.  Therefore, we are made humble(ie. Proper righteousness) by God’s gift (of alien righteousness).  Humility is a response to God’s gift. 
How different are Luther and Aquinas on grace?  Both held that God is the first cause.  On free-will, Luther believed that we have the freedom to sin.  We are at once justified and a sinner.  Both Aquinas and Luther believed in sola gratia.  Luther used material from Augustine and Aquinas. 
Do alien and proper righteousness function like primary and secondary causes?  Yes.  Luther wants to emphasize grace, deemphasizing the virtuous life, or works righteousness.  Being virtuous doesn’t justify one.  To Aquinas, works righteousness is not such a big problem, though he would agree that justification isn’t through it. 

3/29/93
Tillick argued that in the forensic model, God makes us righteous despite the fact that we retain our sinful nature.  God does so by accepting us(justification), and then He makes us acceptable (sanctification).  It is actualized outwardly, spontaneously and freely, against resistence.  Spontaneously due to the change in faith, from which one is no longer preoccupied with one’s self.  It is spontaneous—one follows the law without trying.  Faith=Trust.  In realizing this, one is justified. 
Both the forensic and transformative models are sola gratia.  Luther is Augustinian (Platonist) whereas Aquinas is Aristotilian. 
In the forensic mdel, neither pride nor disorientation are primary; rather, sin, or the lack of belief, is primary.  The basic condition of sinfulness is faithlessness, which leads to anxiety.  Sin as non-belief leads to anxiety.  This idea is linked to modern existentialism (Kiekagaard and Hiedeger).  Possible ways to respond include self-assertion and fearfulness (dependence upon ideolatry).  Luther opposed these responses, responding instead that through law comes the knowledge of sin.  We should be liberated from law as well as sin.  Self-centeredness makes us rebellious.  Beyond Augustine, Luther argued that anxiety is intensified through the law.  An anxious effort to follow the law, and an anxious despair from not following the law are caused by the law.  So, a state of faithlessness and anxiety is intensified by the law.  Augustine and Luther argued that our highest virtues are our worst sin.  Self-righteousness is based on anxiety which refuses to recognize itself.  Sanctification is not from the law, but by sponstaneously doing good works.  Resistance to it is due to the sin of Adam. Augustine and Luther did not hold a spirit-body dualism, though they saw the flesh as self-centeredness and they believed in sola gratia.  Luther emphasized the ‘new creation’ in justification, which spontaneously does good acts.  But, this new self is against the old self, and this conflict is never resolved.  Luther views the process of sanctification as an intensification of the conflict with the old self.  The self is no longer justified as itself.  The self is relational to God, sin and the devil.   Wilford Joest wrote on the excentric self, fighting against the old self.
Luther wrote on simultaneous justification and pecator.  We are simultaneously wholly righteous and wholly sinner.  Augustine didn’t claim this.  For Luther, even our best deeds are sinful.  For instance, we take pride in our selflessness.  Our nature doesn’t change.  Even the best saints do good acts in sin. The Council of Trent condemned sola fide without rejecting sola gratia

3/31/93
The Renissiance and Reformation were polemically related to their preceeding years in the Middle Ages.  The 1600’s saw the rise of science in a new age.  Reform began in Germanic lands, which were relatively disorganized so more money was taken out of them to RomeFrance, Spain, and England, in contrast, had states, and thus nationalism.
By 1523, Erasmus, whose aim was good conduct (humanistic) and who retained some freedom of will (a role in justification, though grace does more), didn’t agree with Luther.  In The Bondage of the Will, Luther is upset about Erasmus, seeing him as being a neo-plagian.  For Luther, God is the sole cause of our justification.  God is even the cause of our resistence, even though God does not cause us to sin.  Luther could be read as a universalist and for double-predestination.  Luther was unsystematic in his thinking, so it is difficult to come up with a coherent picture of him.  Luther was pastoral and a rhetorian, focused on rescuing people from despair.  Sola fide alone is comforting.  To Luther, theology as the grammer of faith never reaches the truth; rather, truth is reached by preaching and praying (not by logical arguments).  So it is hard to see a standard order or pattern in his theology, including for his doctrine of sola scriptura.

4/2/93
By the late 1500’s, Aquinas’ view was still not common.  Double predestination had become known from Luther’s Bondage of the Will
Luther emphasized the literal reading of scripture, and advocated the use of early creeds to interpret it. For instance, Luther took literally the passage that all believers are priests.  So he attacked Richard of St. Victor’s allegorical theme of transformation by grace.  Luther emphasized what justification means in ordinary life in line with justification by faith.  Bible stories make this concrete, being legitimate to the extent that they contain ‘Christ’.  He viewed scripture as the written word of the Trinitarian God giving Jesus Christ.  Luther distinguished between law and the gospel, salvation being in the latter as free forgiveness.  This was not old vs new testament; rather, he distinguished between the commandments and the promises.  Luther deemphasized the epistle of James because of the emphasis there on one’s own works in justification. 
Luther on Law: The purpose of law is to reveal sin so as to drive us to Christ.  There are two purposes of law.  First, civil.  To organize life in social situations (so it is in the Church too).  Key: order is to be maintained.  Second, universally applicable natural law to be applied in particular contexts.  In both of these purposes, law has been distorted by sin.  Luther was against canon law, as people saw it as too complex. 
Luther vs. Aquinas:
Luther used the forensic model whereas Aquinas had used the transformative model.  Luther’s aim was consulation for consciences whereas Aquinas’s aim was contemplation of God.  Luther claimed sola gratia (alien/imputed) and sola fides, wherein we are wholly justified and wholly sinner (a bi-located ‘relational self’).  Aquinas saw it in terms of a changed substantial self (partly justified/partly sinner) of infused/inherent grace formed by love (assensus).  Luther saw sin as total helplessness (unfaith) whereas Aquinas saw sin as aimlessness (disorder).  Luther saw no freedom in the will, whereas Aquinas saw freedom in the will, but it is wholly dependent upon God’s initial causality.  Whereas Luther believed in monergism (God as the sole cause), thus leading to double predestination, Aquinas believed in panergism (all causing), thus believing in single predestination.  Luther saw God as univocal but paradoxical, whereas Aquinas saw God as unified (analogical). 
In contrast, Erasmus was interested in good conduct (morality).  He saw God as the moral rewarder and punisher (univocal and non-pardoxical).  He saw God as partly causeing (synergism), thus having foreknowledge.   So our wills are partly independent. 

4/2/93: Discussion
Luther claims that any choice that is made outside of faith is sin.  So freedom is to do the good, the very possibility of which is granted by God.  The only good deeds are from good motives which come from the love of God.  So one needs faith to know what is right and to have the right motive.  Proper righteousness is subsequent to justification, flowing out as a consequence of grace.  There is no room for our independent agency; everything that happens is from God’s will.  But what about evil?  Luther does not provide a theodicy. 
Because God has the freedom, is he a judging, wrathful God?   Luther claims that God is a saving God.  Both are accurate, due to Luther’s view favoring double predestination.  One need not worry about whether one will be saved or damned as it has already been decided. 
According to Aquinas, baptism erases the effect of original sin.  After this, cooperative grace, so some free will.  Luther rejects cooperative grace and free will, yet not determinate.  We are not free to resist grace, yet we are responsible for our own sin.  A dialectic.  Luther doesn’t deny freedom of choice in civil matters; rather, it’s just that we can’t make choices about justification.  Moral righteousness is a gray area, between civil and proper righteousness.  Luther claims that grace is needed for moral righteousness.  So keep separate the moral and political realms. 
Luther claims that one who is justified wants to do the law, not because good works merit.  Luther is Christocentric, not saying much about the Holy Spirit.  The function of the law (commandments) is to guide one to the gospel (promises), which in turn leads one to Christ.  Some books in the Bible are relatively less important, given this view: James, Revelation, Ester, Hebrews, and Jude.  Other books are more salient, such as John, Romans, Galatans, and Aphesians. 
George Casmin claims there are four senses in which scripture can be interpreted.  Luther stresses the literal sense (historic).  He is against spiritualism, including allegory (something in the text corresponds to something else), anagogical (theological), and tropological (moral).

4/5/93
Scripture vs. Sacraments:
Zwangli and Luther had a dispute over the Lord’s Supper and were the major cause of scism within the Reformation.
On the Lord’s Supper, there are three main groups of texts from scripture:
  1. Accounts of the Lord’s Supper   (1 Cor 11, Mt, and Lk)
  2. The flesh/spirit relationship (Jn 6:63)
  3. Reception of the elements (1 Cor 10-11)
And one creedal statement: Jesus Christ is the ascended Lord.
Luther rejected transubstantiation as a philosophical doctrine not in scripture.  So, contrary to Aristotle, though Luther made use of Aristotle in other areas.  Luther was against reason invading theology (against the humanistic renaissance).  He sounds like an irrationalist, yet he does use philosophical arguments on some issues.  He argued that transubstantiation involves needless multiple miracles.  Why have two(Jesus’ body and blood, and the absence of bread and wine) when scripture only has one(body and blood)
Zwingli was against Eucharistic Realism.  He argued that the presence of the body and blood of Jesus in the bread and wine is idolatrist (confines or identifies the divine with something physical and finite).  So he is against the ceremonies and reverence of the Eucharist.  Luther, in contrast, was not opposed to the ceremony.  Elemental realism.  Hoen pointed out that ‘is’ in the bible can signify rather than identify.  Luther admits this possibility (but says not necessarily).  The bread and wine signify the presence of the body and blood of Christ.   But unless it is necessary to interpret ‘is’ as signifying, don’t.  Key: the incarnation, Christ’s divinity, is not a symbol but is present in his humanity.  So, his body and blood are present in the bread and wine. 
Zwingli uses proof and text for a spiritual interpretation of communion, without the presence of the body and blood in the bread and wine.  So he is a dualist: the soul (spirit) v. body(flesh).  In this sense, Zwingli is a platonist.  Spiritual communion refers to all flesh and all spirit—referring to a relationship rather than to a presence.  Luther claims that this means that ‘is as signify’ is not necessary.
According to Zwingli, what happens to the congregation, as the body of Christ, is what is important.  Faith is a grace given prior to the celebration of the Eucharist.  The receptionist position; faith as a precondition.  To Luther, the Eucharist is by grace; it forgives sins.  It is the promise and gift of himself, not conditional on faith.  Faith is not prior to the gift. If it were, faith would be works righteousness.  The gift, received via faith, is independent of faith. 
Luther believed in mandicatio impiorum (infidelium): unbelievers also receive the body and blood in the Eucharist.  Zwingli: no.
Zwingli argued that the incarnation involved the finite nature and divinity together metaphorically.  If Jesus remains human/finite after the resurrection, then he is limited spacially and temporally so he is not in our time and space. So he could not be truly present in the bread and wine.
According to Luther, there are three ways that something can be present:
  1. Circumscriptively (having boundaries)
  2. Definitively (in a space and time, but not locateable)  Jesus.
  3. Repletively (makes jumps in time and space, so present everywhere) Jesus.
To Luther, Jesus in the Eucharist is present repletively.  As the right hand of God, Jesus is everywhere, yet not available everywhere anytime due to the incarnation.

4/7/93
Luther: the body and blood are signs of a present reality.  The bread and wine, and body and blood, are instruments/vehicles to bring Christ within.  We actually receive the signs of unification with Jesus.
Zwingli: the body and blood are signs of an absent reality.  Sacraments are a means of the proclamation (a means of grace).
Patristic worship being around the sacraments led to theological changes.  New to the reformation, changes in beliefs (lex credendi) led to changes in the liturgy (lex orandi).  In the twentieth century, more was known about the patristic practices and beliefs.  We now know that both Luther and Trent were away from patristic practices and beliefs.  So there has been a movement back to the patristic, with more unification seen.  In the Middle Ages, there was a radical separation between the Eucharist as sacrifice and Communion (congregational groups).  The Mass came to be seen as having magical power and linked to sacrifice.  This was abused for profit, as people paid for benefits. 
A fundamental problem: works righteousness.  So, legitimate reforms.  To Luther, the fundamental problem of the Church was works righteousness in the Eucharistic sacrifice.  So the reform was to shift the meaning of the Eucharist from sacrifice to communion.  In the late middle ages, communion was infrequent.  When done, most people didn’t take it more than once per year.  To Luther, communion had to be to a congregation.  So, he advocated increased frequency of it. 
The Catholic Church saw grace going to communicants.  Zwingli saw the elements used as expressing signs to remember the cross.  So it is something good that we do (to remember the cross).  Luther saw this approach as works righteousness.  Calvin sided with Luther, but agreed with Zwingli.  Body and blood is with God, outside of our space and time.  Yet, the Eucharist is a gift from god so body and blood are not localized (not elemental realism).  The Eucharist, to Calvin, is an efficacious sign (not real presence) toward union with God, so to feed upon.  So, a spiritual communion with Christ, the emphasis being in the relationship between God and the individual.  So Calvin saw the Eucharist as the occasion for the union.  Real presence on the occasion of the union. 
Baptism:
In patristic times, it was seen as union with Christ.  In the Late Medieval period, it was thought to remove original sin.  Luther saw it as giving faith (infants baptized have faith).  Zwingli saw it as a sign of membership.  Calvin saw it as a seal, confirming and strengthening faith, taking effect as the infant grows up.

4/8/93: Discussion
Think of the trinity as follows:each person participates in each Godly function; each person is ‘chair’ in a specific area.  The trinity was not an issue in the Reformation.
Calvin:
Knowledge of God is in us, according to Calvin, but is not sufficient for salvation.  Needed is the knowledge of God for me via revelation (e.g. Christ died for me).  See, John Dillenberger, John Calvin.
Faith and Love: The priority of God’s action.  It is necessary in order to love God, knowing that God loves us.  Aquinas claimed that faith is prior to love (unfirmed faith).  To Calvin, knowledge is not faith or piety.  Faith is knowledge and personal relationship to God and sanctification of Christ’s spirit (grace).  Calvin emphasizes the spirit, whereas Luther didn’t.  To Calvin, true piety is not separate from one’s faith.  Not justified by good works, but Calvin’s emphasis is on the imperative of the Christian life. 
Humans love the glory of God via natural and revealed knowledge.  This is to love the beauty of God, in the aesthetic sense.  Knowledge of self reveals the work of God (in us). Life of faith involves the human experience, so you can’t separate the human experience of faith from knowledge of God.  Calvin emphasizes experience.

4/12/93
Repressed reformers:
  1. Waldensians (Peter Waldo, late 1100’s)  Opposed a hierarchical church; became Calvinists.
  2. Moravians (Wyclif, 1384d; John Huss, 1415d(Hussites))  Anti-papal (Wyclif), Calvinist (Huss), and Lutheran/Reformed combo (Court Zinzmdorf).  Zinzmdorf (1760d) founded the present Moravian Church, emphasizing piety and missions.
  3. Mennonites (Anabaptists; eg. Menno Simons, 1559d.)  Zwingli (sacraments as testimony of one’s faith).  He eliminated infant baptism.  Anabaptists have firm discipline, high standards, and their church life is influenced by medieval monasticism.  Total pacifism, no oaths, and separation from the world (no government or judicial posts).  The Amish are conservative Anabaptists.  The Anabaptists were associated with the peasant revolt and thus were persecuted.  The civil authority proclaimed rebaptism a blasphemy with the penalty being death.
These were Trinitarian Christians.  They were heretical movements for left-wing reform. 
Radical Reformers included the Anabaptists, Spiritualists, and Rationalists(anti-trinitarians)
They opposed the sociopolitical establishment, as they were antiestablishment radicals.
Calvinists thought of themselves as mainstream Catholics.  Calvin himself executed an anti-trinitarian. 
Calvin emphasized the first 600 years of the Church, a time in which Augustine’s thought was emphasized.  Anglicans, Lutheran, and Reformers adhere to patristics.  Luther was of the first generation of reformers. He wanted to remain in the Roman Catholic Church, though he was against papal territory.  He wanted the lay people to be more involved in the Church’s activities.  He did not have a theology of the church (ecclesiology), with changed politics as a result. Calvin was a second generation reformer.  He began six years after Luther.  Calvin thought the Roman Church had lost its right to be the Church.  He provided an ecclesiology (presby), but was toerant to an episcopacy.  Unlike Luther, Calvin was not concerned about the terrified conscience.  Like Luther, Calvin was sola fide.  But not as an answer to the terrified conscience.  Rather, he looked to rising above the world to union with God (happiness).  Jesus was how to get up there.  Reconciled God’s justice and mercy (using Anselm’s atonement).  Predestination is not central to Calvin, nor is the relation between God and man.
Calvin’s principles:
Restoration of the image of God via union with Jesus Christ.  The universe is like an mirror: the glory of God is reflected to the eyes of faith via scripture.  Angels are the messengers of God.  Humans are the highest created beings, not just because of the incarnation.  To the degree that humans turn to God, as the responsibility of our whole being, we are images, or reflections of, God. Gratitude makes humans into the image of God.  Gratitude is a gift, dependent on God.  The desire to do God’s will, involving obedience and praise.  Sin is the destruction of the image of god.  The reflection mirrored is distorted by sin, so it is not total.  These is some sense of divinity in everyone, yet without obedience.  Dissatisfied with life, we seek satisfaction in making up an image (idols).

4/14/93
Sensus Divinatatus: sense of divinity
Aquinas claimed that humans could have some knowledge of God, abstracting from concrete conditions.  Using scripture, he gave five philosophical arguments for God’s existence.  Aquinas was contemplative.  Calvin, on the other hand, was self-involved. He claimed that some innate apriori (Platonist) knowledge of God is available, but is useless for salvation.  Calvin, like Aristotle and Augustine, was interested in practical knowledge of God.  We create idols and religions to fill our dissatisfaction (which is due to sin).  This is not good; instead, we should turn to God in trust.  Calvin claimed that glimmers of God’s glory is in human nature, though in a distorted way.  Sin (ingratitude) leads to ignorance.  Luther saw sin as unfaith/distrust.  Augustine saw sin as turning toward lower goods.  Aquinas saw sin as a lack of direction, or orientation to meaning.
According to Calvin, the focus should be on union with God. A mystical union, at the beginning (rather than at the end).  For this, faith, forgiveness and reconciliation are necessary. Faith is the instrumental cause of the union.  Faith is the sure knowledge of God, firm and certain, involving trust and praise.  Luther saw faith primarily as trust and reliance.
Jesus Christ alone is the perfect image of God.  He was perfectly obedient to God, which led him to the Cross.  Chris is perfect humanity and God; a priest, king and prophet. 
Repentance is a change of mind, involving mortification (being killed; sorrow) and vivification (being revived; new life; sanctification).  Like Augustine (and more so than Luther), Calvin emphasized the struggle to obey God.  Luther emphasized liberation from law as sanctification as a struggle between our own spontaneity and non-spontaneity, leading to progress in learning and trust.  To Calvin, the lack of spontaneity  in loving God is a sign of our imperfection.  Even the greatest saints sin.  But it is a progressive struggle (like Augustine).  It is a sign that the work of God is within us.  To Luther, it is a sign that we are still sinners. 
Calvin saw justification as God accepting us, not due to a change within us.  Even though we sin, it is due to the righteousness of Jesus Christ.  So justification is an imputation of Jesus’ righteousness to us.  Luther had a different order: Repentence (mortification) leads to justification (faith) which leads to sanctification (vivification/union).  Calvin claimed in contrast that you can’t repent unless you already have faith.  Repentance leads to justification which leads to sanctification.  Luther: law leads to despair which leads to turning to Christ by faith (justification).  To Calvin, justification is not due to the struggle to be good.  It is a guide against pride, whereas for Lutehr it is consolation against the terrified conscience. 
Predestination for Calvin plays the same role as it does for Luther.  God has elected those who believe.  We all resist; the work of the Holy Spirit gets some of us beyond this resistance.  God is equally responsible for resistence and overcoming resistence (double predestination). 
In general, Luther and Calvin had different approaches, but are not contradictory. 

4/16/93
Council of Trent:
The reformers were able to show that the Church had departed from sola gratia and had embraced semi-plagianism.  At Trent, the Church was against the semi-plagianism.  In the early 1900’s, Harnack claimed that the late medieval Church had indeed been semi-plagean.  The consensus from dialogue at the end of the twentieth century between Lutherans, Anglicans, and Catholics resulted in the consensus that there was no contradiction between the reformers and Trent as both were sola gratia, with differences only in emphasis. 
Reform had actually started before the Reformation in an indigenous reform movement from within the Catholic Church.  In Spain the government controlled the ecclesiastical structure.  This eliminated abuses in the Church there, so there was no Lutherianism there (further reform was not necessary).  But it led to zealous fanaticism (the Spanish inquisition).  But in Florence, Savonarola was burned before the reformation began for preaching repentence. She changed the pattern of life there. Pope Alexander VI declared her to be a heretic.  In 1509, the Oratory of Divine Love, a group of laity, emphasized sola fide. 
In 1541, there was a caucus of the Catholic and Lutheran groups in hopes of avoiding a schism.  Contrarena led the Catholic group, whereas Melenthan led the Lutherans.  There was agreement on sola fide: in justification, one trusts only God (not oneself).  Justification involves an inward transformation.  So the final judgment was double justification: trust in God (alien righteousness) and inner transformation (infused righteousness).  This distinguished between ontolological (transformative model) and existential (alien righteousness).  But neither Luther nor Rome liked the idea of double justification.  To Luther, it left open works righteousness.  The contemporary Catholic position is that the forensic metaphor breaks down when God lets people ‘out of jail’.  God’s declaration accomplishes God’s verdict.  So the declaration and inward transformation are connected (more so than at Regensburg).
1545 Trent.  Five years after Regensburg.  It was a reforming council, on discipline such as selling indulgences and to require seminaries.  The council also redefined Catholic dogma, which helped Catholics gain ground in the late 1500’s.  Neo-plagianism was rejected in Canons 2 and 3.  It was an attempt to minimalize those excluded yet without going beyond the Catholic position.  It failed.  The reformation positions that were rejected can be seen as characatures of the protestant position.  Calvin read Trent according to the authors’ intentions (trying to deny Lutheranism and Calvinism).  So Calvin tried to find the most schismatic interpretation of Trent.  According to Lindbeck, ,if Trent had been read charitably, it would not be seen as inconsistent with Luther or Calvin.  For instance, Trent can be read as advocating not trusting in one’s own merits, it adopted an incropratist (infused grace) view as the cause of merit (so trust God entirely). We do his gifts in merit, so trust God entirely.  Canons 12-14: don’t trust self (not justification by faith alone).  Calvin also said don’t trust yourself. Both condemn faith in faith.  Canon 25: sin in every good work, so forgiveness is needed for even our best acts.  So, the canons do not exclude the reformation.  Trent and the Reformation need not have been read as being contradictory.

4/16/93: Discussion
The relation between justification and sanctification is central to understanding Calvin.  Justification is instantaneous, by Christ alone.  Sanctification is at the same time and later, progressive and continuous.  Election depends on God’s choice, on the cross.  Calvin uses double predestination so people won’t worry about it.  Jesus’ act is only for the elect.  Some people are going to hell; Jesus didn’t suffer for them.  Salvation and damnation are both done for the glory of God.  We don’t know if we are saved, yet some have some assurance by having done good works. 
Knowledge of God is distinct from faith.  Knowledge of God, from nature: that there is a creator.  It makes me know something about myself—that I am not God.  From my unworthiness, we gain a sense of our need of God.
Formed faith is acquired with charity, whereas unformed faith is without charity.  To Aquinas, formed faith is necessary for salvation.  Calvin includes unformed faith, because he does not like the distinction.  Formed faith is different from knowledge of God( that God exists and is the creator).  Formed faith leads us to realize that God is benevolent.  Then, we can participate with Christ (union with Christ, Christ becomes in us).  Faith is the inward embrace.  In using this mystical transformative language, Calvin is not just forensic (God declaring that one is righteous). 
Christ on the cross is the locus of our salvation.  In sanctification, good works are the fruit of being justified.  Effort suggests the fruit.  The struggle suggests Christ within, from divine initiative.  This is not works righteousness.  Luther emphasizes justification more than Calvin does.  Luther uses the forensic model, stressing forgiveness at once. 

4/19/93
Guest Lecturer

At the time of the Reformation, there was a renewal of religious orders and reform from within in Spain.  In the 1400’s, there had been the Spanish Inquisition, against heretics in southern France, decendents of Jews and Muslems who had converted to Christianity, and against any in a fervent renewal movement (St. John of the Cross, and Ignatious of Loyola were investigated). 
Mysticism spirituality:
Teresa of Abela (1500’s) was a nun.  She wrote Teaching and Instruction in the Life of Prayer and Reform of an Order.  She pointed to the inner struggle involved in living a Christian life, there being a gap between appearance and reality (of self to others).  Her emphasis was on dependence on grace (from Augustine).  From grace comes efforts at prayer. 
Are we passive, manipulated by God?  Resistence is possible to union with God, but not to rapture with God(intimacy of God’s overpowering).  The complex interaction between the person and God is not a question of resistability; rather, it is of God’s choice.
Grace:
Grace transforms, making one humble and aware of our need for God.  Grace is forensic, expressing the condition of the sinner while being righteous.  There are two struggles, one within the person (human striving) and between God and the person which emphasizes God’s grace overwhelming human effort.  These two struggles are a paradox of our own individual effort (striving) and divine assistance. But human striving is really God working through the person.
Ignatius (1491-1556):
He was a soldier, wounded in 1521.  Upon his conversion, he was torn between being a soldier and a follower of Christ.  He chooses the latter, incorporating elements of a soldier’s life.  He emphasized study and pilgrimages, spiritual discipline (becomes the Jesuit discipline), the spirit of the will, the break with stoicism, spiritual exercises, intense meditation on scenes involving Jesus, and conversation(prayer) with God.  He wanted to radicalize the alternatives of being either with God or not.  A clear-cut choice in meditation, using the imagination.  To form the will, one is asked to choose.  Three degrees of commitment—different degrees of holding something back.  There is a psychological difference between thinking of Jesus and being there with him, the latter being conducive to action.  Contemplation in action.  He polarizes and simplifies the world, a struggle between God and satan.   The spiritual practice includes rules on vigils, fasting, and pilgrimages in order to pray and act.  Rules also on obedience to the Church.  The Church=Christ.  So being obedient to the Church is to be obedient to Christ.  Ignatius acknowledged predestination, and claimed that faith and grace are important, though he did not mention the reformers.  He tried to balance our dependence on God with the idea that Christian life means a certain way of life.  Unlike Luther, Ignatius is concerned about laxity, yet he does not want to say human effort is necessary.
Teresa emphasizes the gift of grace (contemplation), whereas Ignatius emphasizes reforming of the will so actions will change. 
The mystical theology maintains that experiences in Christian life leads to grace.

4/21/93
Augustine:
Strong—double predestination and sola gratia.  Calvin, Jansonius(1638), and Pascal
Moderate—single predestination and sola gratia.  Aquinas, Luther Ignatius, and Bellarmine(1621)
Semi—grace and free-will. Molina (1600): prevenience of grace; free-will used to cooperate.

Then, a shift to Justification.  The Catholic Church used a transformative model, then the Reformation used a forensic model.  At Trent, all three forms of Augustine were attempted to be included, but most naturally moderate Augustine.  Trent affirmed the prevenience of grace.  Jansonists took the strong form.  Rome opposed it in 1654.  Jansonism affirmed that grace is irresistible, that some acts are meritorious; freedom from external compulsion only. So merit is a product of irresistible grace.  Also, Jansonists claimed that it is heretical to deny that crass is irresistible (so the molinists were heretics).  And it is heretical to assert that Christ died for all humans. 
Later Calvinism included Beza (1609d), and Arenus who reacted to Beza in affirming moderate Augustine but leaning toward Semi.  Later, what was called Arminianism was Semi.  John Wesley, for instance.  Reaction against Armanus lead to Dort(1619) in which total depravity, unconditional election, limited atonement, irrestability of grace, and the perseverance of the elect was decreed.  The Westminister Confessions were in 1647.  Lambeth Articles had been in 1595, written by the Archbishop of Canterbury, affirming double predestination. 
Sublapsarianism: decrees of election and rejection follow the Fall.
Supralapsarianism: decrees are antecedent to the means appointed to achieve them.  Predestination is the original intent of God. 

4/23/93
The reformers had a rhetorical theology (proclaimed), even as their concerns differed.  For instance, Luther wanted to deal with terrified consciences, whereas Calvin wanted to promote the Christian good life.  Aristotle’s logic dominated—order a set of premises from which conclusions could be deduced.  For instance, it is claimed in the Westminister Confession that good consequences can be deduced from scripture.  That is, if the internal order of scripture passages can be organized, they can be turned into propositions.  The ‘Protestant Orthodoxy’: turn affirmations of faith into premises.  The Catholic Church used tradition, too, as premises.  Calvin’s argument: from a knowledge of God and self, authority of scripture.  The other reformers claimed the reverse: from the authority of scripture, knowledge of God and self. 
In late Calvinism, faith is an apprehension of God’s goodness through Jesus Christ (as merciful to us).  There is thus a cognitive dimension prior to the fiduciary dimension.  Yet, for Calvin as well as Luther, assurance is faith.  Extrospective (clinging to God’s promises in Jesus Christ, true faith only if one is elected) vs. introspective (experientialism as the basis of knowing whether one has true faith).  Late Calvinism syllogism: if I don’t have faith, then I’m not of the elect (i.e. damned).  If I do have faith, then I am one of the elect.  Late Calvinists saw themselves as damned and stressed repentence in their experience.  If one is repentant, then one is pretty sure of one’s election.  Assurance of election is in terms of doing what one is capable of, being dependent upon God.  Thus, trusting God and Jesus, repenting and living a good Christian life. 

4/23/01: Discussion
Augustine got prevenience of grace from Paul. Then Orange and Cartherage, then Aquinas, Luther and Trent.  At Trent, justification was in terms of prevenience of grace with a human input. 
Sin.  Original sin, then concupiscence (inappropriate desire).  Concupiscence is not itself sin, but if acted upon, it is sin.  It is not necessarily behavior, as the key is mental assent.  Idolatry: putting one’s priorities not in God.  In Luther’s view, there are no good acts.  They are somewhat contrary to concupiscence as they are not in themselves sin.  But Luther doesn’t separate concupiscence and other sinful acts. 
Calvin holds justification and sanctification together. 
Venial sin does not separate us from God, and can be worked out in purgatory(e.g. missing mass).  Mortal sin separates us from God (e.g. murder and adultery)
Trent: transformational: sanctification is longer, after justification.  Transformation with an input of grace.  In contrast, Luther used a forensic model, related to legal matters.  It is a broad category, so the transformational and forensic models are not mutually exclusive in the sense that a theology has both qualities, although in different mixes or to different degrees. 
Justification at Trent was both transformative (emphasized) and forensic (justification by faith).  Faith is necessary but not sufficient for justification.  Canon 9 is against justification by faith if this means nothing else is necessary.  Trent here is closer to Luther than to Calvin.  Trent asserts the reality of grace working in person, plus justification by faith.  So Trent, Calvin and Luther are not necessarily in conflict. 
Grace is from God but is not the same as God.
Eastern Church: divine essence (God’s persons) vs. energies (of what one has in divination—authentic participation in God).  The Western Church was against applying divine essence to us.  To the Western Church, Christianity holds that Jesus Christ has divine essence.  A Unitarian would say that Jesus had energies of God (like us)—this goes beyond a moral theory (e.g. moral teachings). 

4/26/01
Jeremy Taylor was the first mainstream theologian to admit that he disagreed with Augustine.  He was an Anglican who wrote his famous text in 1658.  His context was the English Civil War, ten years before his text.  The thirty year war and the peace of Westfalia were also in his context.  It was not just a religious war. 
 The consensus of interpreting scripture in terms of Augustine was breaking down, to be replaced by modern theology.  Taylor appealed to Luther, used reason(from the Greek and Roman classics), and was traditional in liturgical style.  He argued that the notion of double predestination was obsurd.  Later, pietistic protestants (the puritans) rejected (double) predestination.  The problem for Taylor was Augustine’s understanding of original sin in which God imputes the guilt of Adam to his descendents by God’s own decree in judical terms.  Original sin would then involve guilt for something we didn’t do, or, to be separated from God would be to be guilty.  Taylor argued that the imputation of guilt from Adam makes double predestination necessary.  So, if one is against predestination, one has to deny original sin.  If we are not guilty for original sin, then infants who die before they are baptized will not go to hell.  Lutherans baptized infants with uncertainty, not sure if scripture implies that unbaptized infants go to hell.  Calvin was hopeful about the fate of unbaptized infants.  So Taylor was not Calvinist, but agreed with their hope for unbaptized infants.  Taylor also disagreed with Anselm’s notion of atonement.  Anselm (1600’s) claimed that Jesus bears our punishment (i.e. not satisfaction).  Taylor was against this penal substitution notion.  To Taylor, it undermines the necessity of the atoning Christ and disassociates ideas from sensibility.  The idea of the necessity of Christ’s atoning increased into the 1800’s as the denial of the divinity of Jesus spread into deism.  Did Taylor start this?
At around 1650, a new era of theology began.  Taylor was of marginal importance for this new theology.  Locke was more important.  Theology and Philosophy had been closely integrated until then.  The Church was torn apart by disputes at the time, which generated uncertainty of what constitutes a reliable source of Christian truth.  Rationalism, Pietism (experience), Scripturalism (dogmatic adherence), Church Authority (in isolation), and Science (empiricism).  Protestantism used the first three.  Science did not cause this uncertainty, but was a product of it. 
The study of Christian thought: one can learn both the unity and pluralism in the Christian mainstream.  The mainstream are those for whom Jesus Christ is God with us and in history, witnessed by scripture and interpreted by creeds (eg. Trinity).  Within that mainstream, there have been conflicts (different problems and contexts) and unifications.  Many of the differences have been due to the attempt to bring Jesus Christ into different contexts (and problems).  So differences in theology are due especially to different contexts.  So understand others from the inside (their context) before criticizing them.  This is necessary for reconciliation.  Develop patterns of thought and disposition to understand another from the inside.  The study of history helps.




[1] “For it is God who is at work in you, enabling you both to will and to work for his good pleasure.”
[2] Alternative theologies of love: love, not that which is delightful, but is of the needy; compassion.  And love as the responsibility of gratitude.
[3] FomesPeccati: the effects of original sin; inability to do right.
[4] A neo-platonic ‘reminder’ involves participation in a divine reality (i.e. absorbed in another reality).
[5] On the critics of Anselm, see: McIntyre, John St. Anselm and his Critics, Edinburgh(1954): Oliver & Boyd.
[6] Whereas Anselm uses transaction-exchange justice, Aquinas uses distributive justice (according to worth).